Kuratowski closure axioms

In topology and related branches of mathematics, the Kuratowski closure axioms are a set of axioms that can be used to define a topological structure on a set. They are equivalent to the more commonly used open set definition. They were first formalized by Kazimierz Kuratowski,[1] and the idea was further studied by mathematicians such as Wacław Sierpiński and António Monteiro,[2] among others.

A similar set of axioms can be used to define a topological structure using only the dual notion of interior operator.[3]

Definition

Kuratowski closure operators and weakenings

Let X {\displaystyle X} be an arbitrary set and ( X ) {\displaystyle \wp (X)} its power set. A Kuratowski closure operator is a unary operation c : ( X ) ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} :\wp (X)\to \wp (X)} with the following properties:

[K1] It preserves the empty set: c ( ) = {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (\varnothing )=\varnothing } ;

[K2] It is extensive: for all A X {\displaystyle A\subseteq X} , A c ( A ) {\displaystyle A\subseteq \mathbf {c} (A)} ;

[K3] It is idempotent: for all A X {\displaystyle A\subseteq X} , c ( A ) = c ( c ( A ) ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (A)=\mathbf {c} (\mathbf {c} (A))} ;

[K4] It preserves/distributes over binary unions: for all A , B X {\displaystyle A,B\subseteq X} , c ( A B ) = c ( A ) c ( B ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (A\cup B)=\mathbf {c} (A)\cup \mathbf {c} (B)} .

A consequence of c {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} } preserving binary unions is the following condition:[4]

[K4'] It is monotone: A B c ( A ) c ( B ) {\displaystyle A\subseteq B\Rightarrow \mathbf {c} (A)\subseteq \mathbf {c} (B)} .

In fact if we rewrite the equality in [K4] as an inclusion, giving the weaker axiom [K4''] (subadditivity):

[K4''] It is subadditive: for all A , B X {\displaystyle A,B\subseteq X} , c ( A B ) c ( A ) c ( B ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (A\cup B)\subseteq \mathbf {c} (A)\cup \mathbf {c} (B)} ,

then it is easy to see that axioms [K4'] and [K4''] together are equivalent to [K4] (see the next-to-last paragraph of Proof 2 below).

Kuratowski (1966) includes a fifth (optional) axiom requiring that singleton sets should be stable under closure: for all x X {\displaystyle x\in X} , c ( { x } ) = { x } {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (\{x\})=\{x\}} . He refers to topological spaces which satisfy all five axioms as T1-spaces in contrast to the more general spaces which only satisfy the four listed axioms. Indeed, these spaces correspond exactly to the topological T1-spaces via the usual correspondence (see below).[5]

If requirement [K3] is omitted, then the axioms define a Čech closure operator.[6] If [K1] is omitted instead, then an operator satisfying [K2], [K3] and [K4'] is said to be a Moore closure operator.[7] A pair ( X , c ) {\displaystyle (X,\mathbf {c} )} is called Kuratowski, Čech or Moore closure space depending on the axioms satisfied by c {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} } .

Alternative axiomatizations

The four Kuratowski closure axioms can be replaced by a single condition, given by Pervin:[8]

[P] For all A , B X {\displaystyle A,B\subseteq X} , A c ( A ) c ( c ( B ) ) = c ( A B ) c ( ) {\displaystyle A\cup \mathbf {c} (A)\cup \mathbf {c} (\mathbf {c} (B))=\mathbf {c} (A\cup B)\setminus \mathbf {c} (\varnothing )} .

Axioms [K1][K4] can be derived as a consequence of this requirement:

  1. Choose A = B = {\displaystyle A=B=\varnothing } . Then c ( ) c ( c ( ) ) = c ( ) c ( ) = {\displaystyle \varnothing \cup \mathbf {c} (\varnothing )\cup \mathbf {c} (\mathbf {c} (\varnothing ))=\mathbf {c} (\varnothing )\setminus \mathbf {c} (\varnothing )=\varnothing } , or c ( ) c ( c ( ) ) = {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (\varnothing )\cup \mathbf {c} (\mathbf {c} (\varnothing ))=\varnothing } . This immediately implies [K1].
  2. Choose an arbitrary A X {\displaystyle A\subseteq X} and B = {\displaystyle B=\varnothing } . Then, applying axiom [K1], A c ( A ) = c ( A ) {\displaystyle A\cup \mathbf {c} (A)=\mathbf {c} (A)} , implying [K2].
  3. Choose A = {\displaystyle A=\varnothing } and an arbitrary B X {\displaystyle B\subseteq X} . Then, applying axiom [K1], c ( c ( B ) ) = c ( B ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (\mathbf {c} (B))=\mathbf {c} (B)} , which is [K3].
  4. Choose arbitrary A , B X {\displaystyle A,B\subseteq X} . Applying axioms [K1][K3], one derives [K4].

Alternatively, Monteiro (1945) had proposed a weaker axiom that only entails [K2][K4]:[9]

[M] For all A , B X {\displaystyle A,B\subseteq X} , A c ( A ) c ( c ( B ) ) c ( A B ) {\textstyle A\cup \mathbf {c} (A)\cup \mathbf {c} (\mathbf {c} (B))\subseteq \mathbf {c} (A\cup B)} .

Requirement [K1] is independent of [M] : indeed, if X {\displaystyle X\neq \varnothing } , the operator c : ( X ) ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} ^{\star }:\wp (X)\to \wp (X)} defined by the constant assignment A c ( A ) := X {\displaystyle A\mapsto \mathbf {c} ^{\star }(A):=X} satisfies [M] but does not preserve the empty set, since c ( ) = X {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} ^{\star }(\varnothing )=X} . Notice that, by definition, any operator satisfying [M] is a Moore closure operator.

A more symmetric alternative to [M] was also proven by M. O. Botelho and M. H. Teixeira to imply axioms [K2][K4]:[2]

[BT] For all A , B X {\displaystyle A,B\subseteq X} , A B c ( c ( A ) ) c ( c ( B ) ) = c ( A B ) {\textstyle A\cup B\cup \mathbf {c} (\mathbf {c} (A))\cup \mathbf {c} (\mathbf {c} (B))=\mathbf {c} (A\cup B)} .

Analogous structures

Interior, exterior and boundary operators

A dual notion to Kuratowski closure operators is that of Kuratowski interior operator, which is a map i : ( X ) ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {i} :\wp (X)\to \wp (X)} satisfying the following similar requirements:[3]

[I1] It preserves the total space: i ( X ) = X {\displaystyle \mathbf {i} (X)=X} ;

[I2] It is intensive: for all A X {\displaystyle A\subseteq X} , i ( A ) A {\displaystyle \mathbf {i} (A)\subseteq A} ;

[I3] It is idempotent: for all A X {\displaystyle A\subseteq X} , i ( i ( A ) ) = i ( A ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {i} (\mathbf {i} (A))=\mathbf {i} (A)} ;

[I4] It preserves binary intersections: for all A , B X {\displaystyle A,B\subseteq X} , i ( A B ) = i ( A ) i ( B ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {i} (A\cap B)=\mathbf {i} (A)\cap \mathbf {i} (B)} .

For these operators, one can reach conclusions that are completely analogous to what was inferred for Kuratowski closures. For example, all Kuratowski interior operators are isotonic, i.e. they satisfy [K4'], and because of intensivity [I2], it is possible to weaken the equality in [I3] to a simple inclusion.

The duality between Kuratowski closures and interiors is provided by the natural complement operator on ( X ) {\displaystyle \wp (X)} , the map n : ( X ) ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {n} :\wp (X)\to \wp (X)} sending A n ( A ) := X A {\displaystyle A\mapsto \mathbf {n} (A):=X\setminus A} . This map is an orthocomplementation on the power set lattice, meaning it satisfies De Morgan's laws: if I {\displaystyle {\mathcal {I}}} is an arbitrary set of indices and { A i } i I ( X ) {\displaystyle \{A_{i}\}_{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}\subseteq \wp (X)} ,

n ( i I A i ) = i I n ( A i ) , n ( i I A i ) = i I n ( A i ) . {\displaystyle \mathbf {n} \left(\bigcup _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}A_{i}\right)=\bigcap _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}\mathbf {n} (A_{i}),\qquad \mathbf {n} \left(\bigcap _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}A_{i}\right)=\bigcup _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}\mathbf {n} (A_{i}).}

By employing these laws, together with the defining properties of n {\displaystyle \mathbf {n} } , one can show that any Kuratowski interior induces a Kuratowski closure (and vice versa), via the defining relation c := n i n {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} :=\mathbf {nin} } (and i := n c n {\displaystyle \mathbf {i} :=\mathbf {ncn} } ). Every result obtained concerning c {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} } may be converted into a result concerning i {\displaystyle \mathbf {i} } by employing these relations in conjunction with the properties of the orthocomplementation n {\displaystyle \mathbf {n} } .

Pervin (1964) further provides analogous axioms for Kuratowski exterior operators[3] and Kuratowski boundary operators,[10] which also induce Kuratowski closures via the relations c := n e {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} :=\mathbf {ne} } and c ( A ) := A b ( A ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (A):=A\cup \mathbf {b} (A)} .

Abstract operators

Notice that axioms [K1][K4] may be adapted to define an abstract unary operation c : L L {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} :L\to L} on a general bounded lattice ( L , , , 0 , 1 ) {\displaystyle (L,\land ,\lor ,\mathbf {0} ,\mathbf {1} )} , by formally substituting set-theoretic inclusion with the partial order associated to the lattice, set-theoretic union with the join operation, and set-theoretic intersections with the meet operation; similarly for axioms [I1][I4]. If the lattice is orthocomplemented, these two abstract operations induce one another in the usual way. Abstract closure or interior operators can be used to define a generalized topology on the lattice.

Since neither unions nor the empty set appear in the requirement for a Moore closure operator, the definition may be adapted to define an abstract unary operator c : S S {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} :S\to S} on an arbitrary poset S {\displaystyle S} .

Connection to other axiomatizations of topology

Induction of topology from closure

A closure operator naturally induces a topology as follows. Let X {\displaystyle X} be an arbitrary set. We shall say that a subset C X {\displaystyle C\subseteq X} is closed with respect to a Kuratowski closure operator c : ( X ) ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} :\wp (X)\to \wp (X)} if and only if it is a fixed point of said operator, or in other words it is stable under c {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} } , i.e. c ( C ) = C {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (C)=C} . The claim is that the family of all subsets of the total space that are complements of closed sets satisfies the three usual requirements for a topology, or equivalently, the family S [ c ] {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]} of all closed sets satisfies the following:

[T1] It is a bounded sublattice of ( X ) {\displaystyle \wp (X)} , i.e. X , S [ c ] {\displaystyle X,\varnothing \in {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]} ;

[T2] It is complete under arbitrary intersections, i.e. if I {\displaystyle {\mathcal {I}}} is an arbitrary set of indices and { C i } i I S [ c ] {\displaystyle \{C_{i}\}_{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}\subseteq {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]} , then i I C i S [ c ] {\textstyle \bigcap _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}C_{i}\in {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]} ;

[T3] It is complete under finite unions, i.e. if I {\displaystyle {\mathcal {I}}} is a finite set of indices and { C i } i I S [ c ] {\displaystyle \{C_{i}\}_{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}\subseteq {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]} , then i I C i S [ c ] {\textstyle \bigcup _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}C_{i}\in {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]} .

Notice that, by idempotency [K3], one may succinctly write S [ c ] = im ( c ) {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]=\operatorname {im} (\mathbf {c} )} .

Proof 1.

[T1] By extensivity [K2], X c ( X ) {\displaystyle X\subseteq \mathbf {c} (X)} and since closure maps the power set of X {\displaystyle X} into itself (that is, the image of any subset is a subset of X {\displaystyle X} ), c ( X ) X {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (X)\subseteq X} we have X = c ( X ) {\displaystyle X=\mathbf {c} (X)} . Thus X S [ c ] {\displaystyle X\in {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]} . The preservation of the empty set [K1] readily implies S [ c ] {\displaystyle \varnothing \in {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]} .

[T2] Next, let I {\displaystyle {\mathcal {I}}} be an arbitrary set of indices and let C i {\displaystyle C_{i}} be closed for every i I {\displaystyle i\in {\mathcal {I}}} . By extensivity [K2], i I C i c ( i I C i ) {\textstyle \bigcap _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}C_{i}\subseteq \mathbf {c} \left(\bigcap _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}C_{i}\right)} . Also, by isotonicity [K4'], if i I C i C i {\textstyle \bigcap _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}C_{i}\subseteq C_{i}} for all indices i I {\displaystyle i\in {\mathcal {I}}} , then c ( i I C i ) c ( C i ) = C i {\textstyle \mathbf {c} \left(\bigcap _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}C_{i}\right)\subseteq \mathbf {c} (C_{i})=C_{i}} for all i I {\displaystyle i\in {\mathcal {I}}} , which implies c ( i I C i ) i I C i {\textstyle \mathbf {c} \left(\bigcap _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}C_{i}\right)\subseteq \bigcap _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}C_{i}} . Therefore, i I C i = c ( i I C i ) {\textstyle \bigcap _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}C_{i}=\mathbf {c} \left(\bigcap _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}C_{i}\right)} , meaning i I C i S [ c ] {\textstyle \bigcap _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}C_{i}\in {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]} .

[T3] Finally, let I {\displaystyle {\mathcal {I}}} be a finite set of indices and let C i {\displaystyle C_{i}} be closed for every i I {\displaystyle i\in {\mathcal {I}}} . From the preservation of binary unions [K4], and using induction on the number of subsets of which we take the union, we have i I C i = c ( i I C i ) {\textstyle \bigcup _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}C_{i}=\mathbf {c} \left(\bigcup _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}C_{i}\right)} . Thus, i I C i S [ c ] {\textstyle \bigcup _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}C_{i}\in {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]} .

Induction of closure from topology

Conversely, given a family κ {\displaystyle \kappa } satisfying axioms [T1][T3], it is possible to construct a Kuratowski closure operator in the following way: if A ( X ) {\displaystyle A\in \wp (X)} and A = { B ( X )   |   A B } {\displaystyle A^{\uparrow }=\{B\in \wp (X)\ |\ A\subseteq B\}} is the inclusion upset of A {\displaystyle A} , then

c κ ( A ) := B ( κ A ) B {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A):=\bigcap _{B\in (\kappa \cap A^{\uparrow })}B}

defines a Kuratowski closure operator c κ {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }} on ( X ) {\displaystyle \wp (X)} .

Proof 2.

[K1] Since = ( X ) {\displaystyle \varnothing ^{\uparrow }=\wp (X)} , c κ ( ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(\varnothing )} reduces to the intersection of all sets in the family κ {\displaystyle \kappa } ; but κ {\displaystyle \varnothing \in \kappa } by axiom [T1], so the intersection collapses to the null set and [K1] follows.

[K2] By definition of A {\displaystyle A^{\uparrow }} , we have that A B {\displaystyle A\subseteq B} for all B ( κ A ) {\displaystyle B\in \left(\kappa \cap A^{\uparrow }\right)} , and thus A {\displaystyle A} must be contained in the intersection of all such sets. Hence follows extensivity [K2].

[K3] Notice that, for all A ( X ) {\displaystyle A\in \wp (X)} , the family c κ ( A ) κ {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)^{\uparrow }\cap \kappa } contains c κ ( A ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)} itself as a minimal element w.r.t. inclusion. Hence c κ 2 ( A ) = B c κ ( A ) κ B = c κ ( A ) {\textstyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }^{2}(A)=\bigcap _{B\in \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)^{\uparrow }\cap \kappa }B=\mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)} , which is idempotence [K3].

[K4'] Let A B X {\displaystyle A\subseteq B\subseteq X} : then B A {\displaystyle B^{\uparrow }\subseteq A^{\uparrow }} , and thus κ B κ A {\displaystyle \kappa \cap B^{\uparrow }\subseteq \kappa \cap A^{\uparrow }} . Since the latter family may contain more elements than the former, we find c κ ( A ) c κ ( B ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)\subseteq \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(B)} , which is isotonicity [K4']. Notice that isotonicity implies c κ ( A ) c κ ( A B ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)\subseteq \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A\cup B)} and c κ ( B ) c κ ( A B ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(B)\subseteq \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A\cup B)} , which together imply c κ ( A ) c κ ( B ) c κ ( A B ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)\cup \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(B)\subseteq \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A\cup B)} .

[K4] Finally, fix A , B ( X ) {\displaystyle A,B\in \wp (X)} . Axiom [T2] implies c κ ( A ) , c κ ( B ) κ {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A),\mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(B)\in \kappa } ; furthermore, axiom [T2] implies that c κ ( A ) c κ ( B ) κ {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)\cup \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(B)\in \kappa } . By extensivity [K2] one has c κ ( A ) A {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)\in A^{\uparrow }} and c κ ( B ) B {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(B)\in B^{\uparrow }} , so that c κ ( A ) c κ ( B ) ( A ) ( B ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)\cup \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(B)\in \left(A^{\uparrow }\right)\cap \left(B^{\uparrow }\right)} . But ( A ) ( B ) = ( A B ) {\displaystyle \left(A^{\uparrow }\right)\cap \left(B^{\uparrow }\right)=(A\cup B)^{\uparrow }} , so that all in all c κ ( A ) c κ ( B ) κ ( A B ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)\cup \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(B)\in \kappa \cap (A\cup B)^{\uparrow }} . Since then c κ ( A B ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A\cup B)} is a minimal element of κ ( A B ) {\displaystyle \kappa \cap (A\cup B)^{\uparrow }} w.r.t. inclusion, we find c κ ( A B ) c κ ( A ) c κ ( B ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A\cup B)\subseteq \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)\cup \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(B)} . Point 4. ensures additivity [K4].

Exact correspondence between the two structures

In fact, these two complementary constructions are inverse to one another: if C l s K ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathrm {Cls} _{\text{K}}(X)} is the collection of all Kuratowski closure operators on X {\displaystyle X} , and A t p ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathrm {Atp} (X)} is the collection of all families consisting of complements of all sets in a topology, i.e. the collection of all families satisfying [T1][T3], then S : C l s K ( X ) A t p ( X ) {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {S}}:\mathrm {Cls} _{\text{K}}(X)\to \mathrm {Atp} (X)} such that c S [ c ] {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} \mapsto {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]} is a bijection, whose inverse is given by the assignment C : κ c κ {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {C}}:\kappa \mapsto \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }} .

Proof 3.

First we prove that C S = 1 C l s K ( X ) {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {C}}\circ {\mathfrak {S}}={\mathfrak {1}}_{\mathrm {Cls} _{\text{K}}(X)}} , the identity operator on C l s K ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathrm {Cls} _{\text{K}}(X)} . For a given Kuratowski closure c C l s K ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} \in \mathrm {Cls} _{\text{K}}(X)} , define c := C [ S [ c ] ] {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} ':={\mathfrak {C}}[{\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]]} ; then if A ( X ) {\displaystyle A\in \wp (X)} its primed closure c ( A ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} '(A)} is the intersection of all c {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} } -stable sets that contain A {\displaystyle A} . Its non-primed closure c ( A ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (A)} satisfies this description: by extensivity [K2] we have A c ( A ) {\displaystyle A\subseteq \mathbf {c} (A)} , and by idempotence [K3] we have c ( c ( A ) ) = c ( A ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (\mathbf {c} (A))=\mathbf {c} (A)} , and thus c ( A ) ( A S [ c ] ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (A)\in \left(A^{\uparrow }\cap {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]\right)} . Now, let C ( A S [ c ] ) {\displaystyle C\in \left(A^{\uparrow }\cap {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]\right)} such that A C c ( A ) {\displaystyle A\subseteq C\subseteq \mathbf {c} (A)} : by isotonicity [K4'] we have c ( A ) c ( C ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (A)\subseteq \mathbf {c} (C)} , and since c ( C ) = C {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (C)=C} we conclude that C = c ( A ) {\displaystyle C=\mathbf {c} (A)} . Hence c ( A ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (A)} is the minimal element of A S [ c ] {\displaystyle A^{\uparrow }\cap {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} ]} w.r.t. inclusion, implying c ( A ) = c ( A ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} '(A)=\mathbf {c} (A)} .

Now we prove that S C = 1 A t p ( X ) {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {S}}\circ {\mathfrak {C}}={\mathfrak {1}}_{\mathrm {Atp} (X)}} . If κ A t p ( X ) {\displaystyle \kappa \in \mathrm {Atp} (X)} and κ := S [ C [ κ ] ] {\displaystyle \kappa ':={\mathfrak {S}}[{\mathfrak {C}}[\kappa ]]} is the family of all sets that are stable under c κ {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }} , the result follows if both κ κ {\displaystyle \kappa '\subseteq \kappa } and κ κ {\displaystyle \kappa \subseteq \kappa '} . Let A κ {\displaystyle A\in \kappa '} : hence c κ ( A ) = A {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)=A} . Since c κ ( A ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)} is the intersection of an arbitrary subfamily of κ {\displaystyle \kappa } , and the latter is complete under arbitrary intersections by [T2], then A = c κ ( A ) κ {\displaystyle A=\mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)\in \kappa } . Conversely, if A κ {\displaystyle A\in \kappa } , then c κ ( A ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\kappa }(A)} is the minimal superset of A {\displaystyle A} that is contained in κ {\displaystyle \kappa } . But that is trivially A {\displaystyle A} itself, implying A κ {\displaystyle A\in \kappa '} .

We observe that one may also extend the bijection S {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {S}}} to the collection C l s C ˇ ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathrm {Cls} _{\check {C}}(X)} of all Čech closure operators, which strictly contains C l s K ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathrm {Cls} _{\text{K}}(X)} ; this extension S ¯ {\displaystyle {\overline {\mathfrak {S}}}} is also surjective, which signifies that all Čech closure operators on X {\displaystyle X} also induce a topology on X {\displaystyle X} .[11] However, this means that S ¯ {\displaystyle {\overline {\mathfrak {S}}}} is no longer a bijection.

Examples

  • As discussed above, given a topological space X {\displaystyle X} we may define the closure of any subset A X {\displaystyle A\subseteq X} to be the set c ( A ) = { C  a closed subset of  X | A C } {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (A)=\bigcap \{C{\text{ a closed subset of }}X|A\subseteq C\}} , i.e. the intersection of all closed sets of X {\displaystyle X} which contain A {\displaystyle A} . The set c ( A ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (A)} is the smallest closed set of X {\displaystyle X} containing A {\displaystyle A} , and the operator c : ( X ) ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} :\wp (X)\to \wp (X)} is a Kuratowski closure operator.
  • If X {\displaystyle X} is any set, the operators c , c : ( X ) ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\top },\mathbf {c} _{\bot }:\wp (X)\to \wp (X)} such that
    c ( A ) = { A = , X A , c ( A ) = A A ( X ) , {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\top }(A)={\begin{cases}\varnothing &A=\varnothing ,\\X&A\neq \varnothing ,\end{cases}}\qquad \mathbf {c} _{\bot }(A)=A\quad \forall A\in \wp (X),}
    are Kuratowski closures. The first induces the indiscrete topology { , X } {\displaystyle \{\varnothing ,X\}} , while the second induces the discrete topology ( X ) {\displaystyle \wp (X)} .
  • Fix an arbitrary S X {\displaystyle S\subsetneq X} , and let c S : ( X ) ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{S}:\wp (X)\to \wp (X)} be such that c S ( A ) := A S {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{S}(A):=A\cup S} for all A ( X ) {\displaystyle A\in \wp (X)} . Then c S {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{S}} defines a Kuratowski closure; the corresponding family of closed sets S [ c S ] {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} _{S}]} coincides with S {\displaystyle S^{\uparrow }} , the family of all subsets that contain S {\displaystyle S} . When S = {\displaystyle S=\varnothing } , we once again retrieve the discrete topology ( X ) {\displaystyle \wp (X)} (i.e. c = c {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\varnothing }=\mathbf {c} _{\bot }} , as can be seen from the definitions).
  • If λ {\displaystyle \lambda } is an infinite cardinal number such that λ crd ( X ) {\displaystyle \lambda \leq \operatorname {crd} (X)} , then the operator c λ : ( X ) ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\lambda }:\wp (X)\to \wp (X)} such that
    c λ ( A ) = { A crd ( A ) < λ , X crd ( A ) λ {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\lambda }(A)={\begin{cases}A&\operatorname {crd} (A)<\lambda ,\\X&\operatorname {crd} (A)\geq \lambda \end{cases}}}
    satisfies all four Kuratowski axioms.[12] If λ = 0 {\displaystyle \lambda =\aleph _{0}} , this operator induces the cofinite topology on X {\displaystyle X} ; if λ = 1 {\displaystyle \lambda =\aleph _{1}} , it induces the cocountable topology.

Properties

  • Since any Kuratowski closure is isotonic, and so is obviously any inclusion mapping, one has the (isotonic) Galois connection c : ( X ) i m ( c ) ; ι : i m ( c ) ( X ) {\displaystyle \langle \mathbf {c} :\wp (X)\to \mathrm {im} (\mathbf {c} );\iota :\mathrm {im} (\mathbf {c} )\hookrightarrow \wp (X)\rangle } , provided one views ( X ) {\displaystyle \wp (X)} as a poset with respect to inclusion, and i m ( c ) {\displaystyle \mathrm {im} (\mathbf {c} )} as a subposet of ( X ) {\displaystyle \wp (X)} . Indeed, it can be easily verified that, for all A ( X ) {\displaystyle A\in \wp (X)} and C i m ( c ) {\displaystyle C\in \mathrm {im} (\mathbf {c} )} , c ( A ) C {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (A)\subseteq C} if and only if A ι ( C ) {\displaystyle A\subseteq \iota (C)} .
  • If { A i } i I {\displaystyle \{A_{i}\}_{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}} is a subfamily of ( X ) {\displaystyle \wp (X)} , then
    i I c ( A i ) c ( i I A i ) , c ( i I A i ) i I c ( A i ) . {\displaystyle \bigcup _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}\mathbf {c} (A_{i})\subseteq \mathbf {c} \left(\bigcup _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}A_{i}\right),\qquad \mathbf {c} \left(\bigcap _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}A_{i}\right)\subseteq \bigcap _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}\mathbf {c} (A_{i}).}
  • If A , B ( X ) {\displaystyle A,B\in \wp (X)} , then c ( A ) c ( B ) c ( A B ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (A)\setminus \mathbf {c} (B)\subseteq \mathbf {c} (A\setminus B)} .

Topological concepts in terms of closure

Refinements and subspaces

A pair of Kuratowski closures c 1 , c 2 : ( X ) ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{1},\mathbf {c} _{2}:\wp (X)\to \wp (X)} such that c 2 ( A ) c 1 ( A ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{2}(A)\subseteq \mathbf {c} _{1}(A)} for all A ( X ) {\displaystyle A\in \wp (X)} induce topologies τ 1 , τ 2 {\displaystyle \tau _{1},\tau _{2}} such that τ 1 τ 2 {\displaystyle \tau _{1}\subseteq \tau _{2}} , and vice versa. In other words, c 1 {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{1}} dominates c 2 {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{2}} if and only if the topology induced by the latter is a refinement of the topology induced by the former, or equivalently S [ c 1 ] S [ c 2 ] {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} _{1}]\subseteq {\mathfrak {S}}[\mathbf {c} _{2}]} .[13] For example, c {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\top }} clearly dominates c {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{\bot }} (the latter just being the identity on ( X ) {\displaystyle \wp (X)} ). Since the same conclusion can be reached substituting τ i {\displaystyle \tau _{i}} with the family κ i {\displaystyle \kappa _{i}} containing the complements of all its members, if C l s K ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathrm {Cls} _{\text{K}}(X)} is endowed with the partial order c c c ( A ) c ( A ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} \leq \mathbf {c} '\iff \mathbf {c} (A)\subseteq \mathbf {c} '(A)} for all A ( X ) {\displaystyle A\in \wp (X)} and A t p ( X ) {\displaystyle \mathrm {Atp} (X)} is endowed with the refinement order, then we may conclude that S {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {S}}} is an antitonic mapping between posets.

In any induced topology (relative to the subset A) the closed sets induce a new closure operator that is just the original closure operator restricted to A: c A ( B ) = A c X ( B ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} _{A}(B)=A\cap \mathbf {c} _{X}(B)} , for all B A {\displaystyle B\subseteq A} .[14]

Continuous maps, closed maps and homeomorphisms

A function f : ( X , c ) ( Y , c ) {\displaystyle f:(X,\mathbf {c} )\to (Y,\mathbf {c} ')} is continuous at a point p {\displaystyle p} iff p c ( A ) f ( p ) c ( f ( A ) ) {\displaystyle p\in \mathbf {c} (A)\Rightarrow f(p)\in \mathbf {c} '(f(A))} , and it is continuous everywhere iff

f ( c ( A ) ) c ( f ( A ) ) {\displaystyle f(\mathbf {c} (A))\subseteq \mathbf {c} '(f(A))}
for all subsets A ( X ) {\displaystyle A\in \wp (X)} .[15] The mapping f {\displaystyle f} is a closed map iff the reverse inclusion holds,[16] and it is a homeomorphism iff it is both continuous and closed, i.e. iff equality holds.[17]

Separation axioms

Let ( X , c ) {\displaystyle (X,\mathbf {c} )} be a Kuratowski closure space. Then

  • X {\displaystyle X} is a T0-space iff x y {\displaystyle x\neq y} implies c ( { x } ) c ( { y } ) {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (\{x\})\neq \mathbf {c} (\{y\})} ;[18]
  • X {\displaystyle X} is a T1-space iff c ( { x } ) = { x } {\displaystyle \mathbf {c} (\{x\})=\{x\}} for all x X {\displaystyle x\in X} ;[19]
  • X {\displaystyle X} is a T2-space iff x y {\displaystyle x\neq y} implies that there exists a set A ( X ) {\displaystyle A\in \wp (X)} such that both x c ( A ) {\displaystyle x\notin \mathbf {c} (A)} and y c ( n ( A ) ) {\displaystyle y\notin \mathbf {c} (\mathbf {n} (A))} , where n {\displaystyle \mathbf {n} } is the set complement operator.[20]

Closeness and separation

A point p {\displaystyle p} is close to a subset A {\displaystyle A} if p c ( A ) . {\displaystyle p\in \mathbf {c} (A).} This can be used to define a proximity relation on the points and subsets of a set.[21]

Two sets A , B ( X ) {\displaystyle A,B\in \wp (X)} are separated iff ( A c ( B ) ) ( B c ( A ) ) = {\displaystyle (A\cap \mathbf {c} (B))\cup (B\cap \mathbf {c} (A))=\varnothing } . The space X {\displaystyle X} is connected iff it cannot be written as the union of two separated subsets.[22]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Kuratowski (1922).
  2. ^ a b Monteiro (1945), p. 160.
  3. ^ a b c Pervin (1964), p. 44.
  4. ^ Pervin (1964), p. 43, Exercise 6.
  5. ^ Kuratowski (1966), p. 38.
  6. ^ Arkhangel'skij & Fedorchuk (1990), p. 25.
  7. ^ "Moore closure". nLab. March 7, 2015. Retrieved August 19, 2019.
  8. ^ Pervin (1964), p. 42, Exercise 5.
  9. ^ Monteiro (1945), p. 158.
  10. ^ Pervin (1964), p. 46, Exercise 4.
  11. ^ Arkhangel'skij & Fedorchuk (1990), p. 26.
  12. ^ A proof for the case λ = 0 {\displaystyle \lambda =\aleph _{0}} can be found at "Is the following a Kuratowski closure operator?!". Stack Exchange. November 21, 2015.
  13. ^ Pervin (1964), p. 43, Exercise 10.
  14. ^ Pervin (1964), p. 49, Theorem 3.4.3.
  15. ^ Pervin (1964), p. 60, Theorem 4.3.1.
  16. ^ Pervin (1964), p. 66, Exercise 3.
  17. ^ Pervin (1964), p. 67, Exercise 5.
  18. ^ Pervin (1964), p. 69, Theorem 5.1.1.
  19. ^ Pervin (1964), p. 70, Theorem 5.1.2.
  20. ^ A proof can be found at this link.
  21. ^ Pervin (1964), pp. 193–196.
  22. ^ Pervin (1964), p. 51.

References

  • Kuratowski, Kazimierz (1922) [1920], "Sur l'opération A de l'Analysis Situs" [On the operation A in Analysis Situs] (PDF), Fundamenta Mathematicae (in French), vol. 3, pp. 182–199.
  • Kuratowski, Kazimierz (1966) [1958], Topology, vol. I, translated by Jaworowski, J., Academic Press, ISBN 0-12-429201-1, LCCN 66029221.
    • —— (2010). "On the Operation Ā Analysis Situs". ResearchGate. Translated by Mark Bowron.
  • Pervin, William J. (1964), Boas, Ralph P. Jr. (ed.), Foundations of General Topology, Academic Press, ISBN 9781483225159, LCCN 64-17796.
  • Arkhangel'skij, A.V.; Fedorchuk, V.V. (1990) [1988], Gamkrelidze, R.V.; Arkhangel'skij, A.V.; Pontryagin, L.S. (eds.), General Topology I, Encyclopaedia of Mathematical Sciences, vol. 17, translated by O'Shea, D.B., Berlin: Springer-Verlag, ISBN 978-3-642-64767-3, LCCN 89-26209.
  • Monteiro, António (1945), "Caractérisation de l'opération de fermeture par un seul axiome" [Characterization of the operation of closure by a single axiom], Portugaliae mathematica (in French), vol. 4, no. 4, pp. 158–160, MR 0012310, Zbl 0060.39406.

External links

  • Alternative Characterizations of Topological Spaces